Extract from 'Loneliness: In Harm’s Way*' I attended this symposium and these are the verbatim notes of a talk at Brunel University, London on 30th October 2015: The speaker wished to convey four things: (a) that all human
beings are innately and universally lonely; (b) why
this is so; (c) the consequences of loneliness; and (d) what can be done about
it - its remedies!
"The twin principles I propose to defend are that all
we feel, think, say, and do occurs between two emotional and cognitive poles in
human consciousness, between the solipsistic insularity of loneliness and the
intentional desire to transcend it by attaining intimate attachments. The two
terminals of consciousness constitute the dynamics of repulsion and attraction,
which continually guide us through our passions, thoughts, and actions. After
the biological drives for air, water, nourishment, sleep—and before sex---are
met, the most insistent psychological need and motivational drive in human
beings is to secure an intimate relation to other self-conscious creatures,
whether animal, human, or divine. In effect, I wish to replace Freud’s principle
of libidinal energy with the anxiety of isolation.
The first proof that the fear of loneliness is innate can be
demonstrated by citing the writings of Margaret Ribble, Donald Winnicott, John
Bowlby, Rene Spitz, Ana Freud, Dorothy Burlingham, Margaret Mahler, and Harry
Harlow’s experiments with young monkeys, who collectively show that without
sufficient emotional nurturance, infants retreat back toward the womb and even
death. Over half of the deaths of institutionalized children under the age of
one in England during the First World War died (Ruch, 1953; Mijuskovic, 1991).
It was originally called marasmus, hospitalism, or anaclitic depression (Spitz).
It would be extremely important to learn precisely which children died—whether
it was the ones who were nurtured for an extended period of some months by the
mothers; or those who were removed from parental care immediately after birth.
This could tell us the relative severity of the emotional damage and possibly a
means of predicting later problems for the survivors.
At this early point it is helpful to interject the case of a “feral
child” discovered in Florida in 2005. The story begins with a neighbor passing
by a house one day and seeing an emaciated child staring blankly out of a window
with broken glass, a child with hollow, vacant eyes staring beyond the observing
woman unwilling or unable to make any eye contact with her. The concerned woman
reported it to Child Protective Services and two police officers investigated
and found a six-year-old girl, Danielle or Dani, living with her mother and two
much older male siblings. She was extremely thin, seriously undernourished,
covered with sores, wearing filthy diapers, and couldn’t speak. She was confined
to a single room furnished with only a bed. She was immediately removed by the
officers from parental custody, transported to a shelter, and soon thereafter
placed for adoption. Two years later, she was adopted. Today, in 2015, she can
barely talk, does not relate to people, and only tentatively responds to her
adoptive father. The refrigerator has to be locked for otherwise she will eat
everything in it. She remains severely emotionally impaired or “flat,”
experiences fits of uncontrollable anger, and prefers to relate to objects
instead of people (Tampa Bay Times, 2005, 2015).
The second proof is grounded in the consideration that no human
being would ever wish to be immortal at the price of being the only
self-conscious creature in a lifeless universe, condemned to exist eternally
alone in the infinite expanses of space and time.
“Fear of the Lord is the beginning of wisdom” (Proverbs, 9:10). To
be estranged from God is the ultimate terror. Consider St. Augustine’s Prayer
to the Lord: “Who will give me help so that I may rest in you? Who will give me
help… so that I may forget my evils and embrace you, my one good? Have pity on
me, so that I may speak. What am I myself to you, that you command me to love
you, and grow angry and threaten me with mighty woes unless I do?” (Augustine,
1960). The ultimate woe, of course, is absolute and eternal loneliness, a
perpetual estrangement from God.
Kant relates the story of a miserly man whose complete disdain and
contempt for humanity earns him a visit from the Angel of Death, who tells him
he is condemned to be transported to dwell eternally in the farthest and darkest
reaches of the universe alone forever without any human or divine contact (Kant,
2011). It would be like being buried alive except his tomb would be the whole
universe. We recall Sophocles’ Antigone, whose sentence is to be entombed alive
for disobeying the laws of the State and whose fate is only avoided by her
suicide. In my clinical practice, I had an anxiety client, who was brought to
the clinic by his spouse, and spent the entire session crumpled in a corner. He
described his panic attacks as being buried alive.
In Kierkegaard, Abraham’s fear of estrangement is directly related
to God’s command to sacrifice Isaac, his beloved son. Through a leap of
paradoxical faith, Abraham makes a religious choice to comply with God’s
command. His act is beyond understanding; it defies reason, human compassion,
and all comprehension; it must grasp a contradiction, namely that Isaac will be
both saved and sacrificed. Now if we compare and contrast Abraham’s “leap of
faith,” his religious decision, with Agamemnon’s ethical choice of sacrificing
Iphigenia so the Greek fleet could sail to Troy, we see that we can understand
Agamemnon; we know his motive; but who can comprehend Abraham? He cannot even
tell Sarah what he intends to do; it is beyond human expression and language
(Kierkegaard, 1974)
The fear of the Lord and being eternally abandoned is the beginning
of human wisdom. In short, “We are lonely from the cradle to the grave and
perhaps beyond” (Joseph Conrad, An Outcaste of the Islands). From the day we are
born to the day we expire, we struggle to secure intimacy and escape from our
lonely condition.
Loneliness intrinsically means a sense of separation. The opposite
of separation is a sense of intimacy, belonging, or togetherness with another
self-conscious agent beyond our self.
There are five developmental sources of human separation. First,
there is the fetus’ biological ejection from the womb (object-object separation;
Freud’s initial state of anxiety (Freud, 1960, 48; Mahler, 1975). Initially the
“self” experiences something akin to an unbounded immediate “oceanic feeling,”
an “undifferentiated oneness” (Freud, 1961a, 12). Similarly, William James in
his Principles of Psychology (1950), describes the newborn infant as “assailed
by eyes, ears, nose, skin, and entrails at once feeling it all as one great
blooming, buzzing confusion,” as a differenceless, indiscriminate unity, a
sensory amalgam of undifferentiated qualities, a fused confusion of
kaleidoscopic sights and a mélange of cacophonic sounds. Long before James,
however, Hegel had previously characterized the primordial dawn of incipient
consciousness, in the Section of Sense-Certainty in the Phenomenology, in
similar terms as a non-temporal “pure immediacy,” an indistinguishable unity of
infantile awareness, of feelings and sensations devoid of any cognitive
discrimination (Hegel, 1977).
The second stage occurs when the conscious subject emotionally and
cognitively separates its self from the external world (subject-object
separation=self-consciousness). This happens in Kant when the self actively
distinguishes itself from a world of objects both transcendentally and
empirically in the two Deductions of the categories (Kant, 1958; Mijuskovic,
2010, 2012, 2015). In order to be self-conscious, the self must be able to
distinguish its self, separate its self from the world of objects. The
subject-object relation is thus mutually constituted in self-consciousness as a
synthetic a priori relation (see Chart). Similarly, in Freud, the infant
transitions from the unbounded feeling of undifferentiated oneness by relating
to his mother’s breast as an inanimate object. For instance, the baby in the
crib reaches out to touch the moon only to realize it is not part of its
self.
Further reflection tells us that the adult’s ego-feeling cannot have been
the same from the beginning. It must have gone through a process of development,
which cannot, of course, be demonstrated but which admits of being constructed
with a fair degree of probability. An infant at the breast does not as yet
distinguish his ego from the external world as the source of the sensations
flowing in upon him. He gradually learns to do so, in response to various
promptings. He must be very strongly impressed by the fact that some sources of
excitation, which he will later recognize as his own bodily organs, can provide
him with sensations at any moment, whereas other sources evade him from time to
time—among them what he desires most of all, his mother’s breast---and only
reappear as a result of his screaming for help. In this way, there is for the
first time set over against the ego an ‘object’, in the form of something which
exists ‘outside’ and which is only forced to appear by a special action (Freud,
1961, page 14; italic mine).
Here again we may refer with profit to Dani’s---the feral
child’s---obsession with certain objects, at the expense of forging human
relationships, as she possessively focuses on food alone. At this stage of a
child’s development, loneliness is essentially intra-psychic. The child fears
separation from desired objects. It is object-dependent. This may also provide
us with a clue in regard to elderly hoarders, who anxiously fear being separated
from their valued objects. Their relation is to things as opposed to
persons.
Third, however, as the child develops, the loneliness becomes
interpersonal. The narcissistic self/ego dialectically separates its self from
the mother’s self/ego thus generating conflicts of resistance, assertion, and
hostility between its self and an opposing “other self,” (self/ego versus other
self/ego separation). Additionally, the breast is something the mother can
dynamically offer or withhold at will from the child thus creating interpersonal
struggles, generating in the child a vacillation between fear and anger versus
security and intimacy. The mother demands compliance and the infant resists and
seeks independence. For Hegel--as opposed to Kant--self-consciousness is a
relation between two self-consciousnesses; it is a “fight to the death for
recognition”; the child struggles for independence, freedom, assertion; it
strives to dominate the consciousness of the other self. Powerful feelings of
hostility and anxiety are inevitably generated (Hegel, 1977). Hegel is here
borrowing from Hobbes’ description of human “life as solitary, poor, nasty,
brutish and short”; “a war of all against all” (Leviathan). This dynamic also
serves later as the dialectical ground for Marx’s concept of alienation, for the
worker’s sense of separation from nature, from his labor, from his product, and
from his fellow man through competition for a living wage. As Marx describes it,
man becomes stunted and deformed, dehumanized by machines that enslave him as
well as an economic system which exploits him (Kojeve, 1969). Similarly, the
desire for dominance is expressed in Nietzsche’s “will to power” principle as
well as in Sartre’s phenomenological account of the inherent struggle between
selves, each determined to assert his free existence over that of “the other.”
In the “The Look” passage in Being and Nothingness, Sartre describes a man
spying through a keyhole presumably viewing a lascivious scene in another room
when he is suddenly caught from behind and transformed into a “thing,” the
observer reducing him to an “unfree object,” the sort of despicable person who
spies on others, a “voyeur.” Hegel’s master-slave relation is central as well
in Adler’s conception that each of us is born with an inferiority complex, which
we desperately fight to overcome, to transcend throughout our lives.
Fourth, there is the inevitable frightening anticipation of a final
separation from the rest of humanity by death. Likewise for Freud, death signals
the natural cycle of “separation” and the return of the organic to the
inorganic, to the lifeless, to the inanimate.
The fear of death in melancholia [i.e. loneliness] only admits of one
explanation… [The ego] sees itself deserted by all protective forces and lets
itself die. Here, moreover it is once again the same situation as that which
first underlay the great anxiety-state of birth and the infantile anxiety-state
of longing [i.e. loneliness] due to separation from the protective mother
(Freud, 1960, page 48).
In Freud, the thanatological principle of death is intrinsically
tied to aggression and self-destruction and eventually subtly transferred and
sublimated into competition through sports. Let us not be misled that
competitive sports are merely for physical health. Indeed, if one wishes to
understand American society, one only needs to observe the National Football
League. There are thirty-one losers and only one winner (Mijuskovic,
1992).
Fifth, psychosis is constituted as the self’s self-alienation from
the world and other selves by an internalization of “the other” within so that
one can control the loneliness from inside the self. Indeed, Hegel insists that
we must first understand madness before we can comprehend sanity.
Man alone has the capacity of grasping himself in this complete abstraction
[separation] of the ‘I’. This is why he has, so to speak, the privilege of folly
and madness (Hegel, 1971; Berthold-Bond, 1995).
Conclusion: It is these painful separations that we need to address
and circumvent in so far as we can in order to secure intimacy.
Most current researchers—materialists, empiricists, behaviorists,
and neuroscientists---contend that loneliness is externally caused by
environmental, cultural, and situational conditions, and even by chemical
imbalances in the brain and therefore temporary, transient, and avoidable.
Indeed, the American Psychiatric Association christened the 1990’s as “the
decade of the brain” ( see Diagram of the Brain). By contrast, I argue that
loneliness is internally constituted---not externally caused—within
consciousness by the innate activities and structures of (a) Kantian
self-consciousness and (b) Husserlian intentionality and therefore it is
universal and necessary i.e. a priori, permanent, and unavoidable.
The solitary self emotionally seeks a mutual affective and cognitive
unification or attachment with another self-conscious being through intimacy.
The self intrinsically desires to overcome its sense of solipsistic separation,
isolation, alienation, and estrangement. When this fails, feelings, thoughts,
and fantasies of hostility, anxiety and even murder and suicide inevitably
follow in varying degrees of intensity. Thus the question becomes how to bridge
the chasm between loneliness and intimacy; how to transcend the separation
between insularity and attachment; how to establish a conduit between the
negative and the positive poles outlined above.
One of the most important and ageless questions in the history of
ideas and philosophy revolves around the issue “whether senseless matter can
think?” It is grounded in what Plato calls the “Battle of the Gods against the
Giants,” between the idealists and rationalists against the materialists and
behaviorists (Plato, 1966; Cornford, 1964). It pits Plato against Democritus;
Plotinus against Epicurus; Augustine and Aquinas against Skeptics and Atheists;
Ficino against Valla; Descartes against Hobbes; Leibniz against Locke; Kant
against Hume; Hegel against Marx; Bradley against Mill; Freud against Pavlov;
and Husserl and Sartre against Russell and Ryle.
In order to understand the affective and cognitive roots of
loneliness, we must first define the cluster of opposing principles between the
two warring camps just cited, which consists of theories of reality and
paradigms of consciousness. The first group represents materialism; mechanism;
empiricism; phenomenalism; determinism; behaviorism; the neurosciences; and
indeed the natural sciences in general, which contend that loneliness is caused
by physical conditions as they focus on determinate quantitative, measurable
factors.
By contrast, the second group includes dualism; idealism;
rationalism; phenomenology; and existentialism and represents a humanistic
approach to our sense of negative isolation and it argues that it is constituted
by the innate activities and structures of consciousness as it unfolds, in
contrast to the former set, in qualitative concepts and fluid descriptions.
In what follows, I wish to compare and contrast these two
contrasting theoretical perspectives. The first constellation presents
loneliness as due to external factors: Materialism assumes that all that exists
is reducible to matter plus motion (Hobbes). (But what sense does it make to
assert that the sun, moon, and stars would still shine if there were no sentient
creatures in the universe?) Mechanism declares that everything can be explained
through a chain of unbreakable causes. Determinism holds that everything is
either connected by physical causes, psychological motives, or both (Hobbes
again); not only is there is no freedom but we are and can be controlled by
external forces (Orwell’s 1984). Empiricism argues that all we know is dependent
on precedent sensations; that there is nothing in the mind, which is not first
given in sensation and experience; the mind is like a blank tablet upon which
experience writes (Aristotle, Locke). Phenomenalism, a species of empiricism,
proposes that all “realities,” including “space,” “time,” the “external world,”
the “causal maxim,” the “self,” as well as every conscious state are merely
appearances in the mind, contingent constructions of atomistic sense data; only
mental particulars exist, simple sensations (nominalism). Behaviorism is the
doctrine that everything is reducible to stimulus-response configurations, the
“mind”=brain is like a computer that is programmed from without by external
conditions. Neuroscience maintains that ultimate reality consists of electrons
firing in the brain; consciousness is “linear”; the cause or motion is external
and directed toward the passive, receptive brain. Therapy and treatment are
conducted through “verbal contracts,” operant conditioning, and regimens of
psychiatric medication. (Mijuskovic, 2012, 2015a, 2015b).
The result is that the collective doctrines cited above directly
lead to the Diagnostic Statistical Manual of Psychiatric Disorders’ artificial,
arbitrary classification of symptoms and diagnoses. This materialist,
behaviorist paradigm of “consciousness” is enthusiastically adopted by today’s
neo-phrenologists and neuroscientists, researchers John Cacioppo, Paul and
Patricia Churchland, et al., who transform and reduce “consciousness” into
electrochemical impulses in the brain.
But it is one thing to say that we cannot think without a brain but
quite a different matter to claim that the mind is completely reducible to,
identical with, and/or explainable by brain motions alone. An
electroencephalograph may indicate that the brain is thinking but it cannot tell
us what “it” is thinking. Imagine for a moment that I am giving this as a
lecture in another room in this building and all you see before you is a graph
of my brain spikes and waves projected on a screen. How “meaningful” would that
be? Meanings are not identical to sensations; a random collection of sensations
is just that and no more; it is not a meaning. Neither are relations reducible
to a cluster of fortuitous “associations of ideas” contingently connected by
contiguity and resemblance and “causality” being translated by the imagination
into a psychological “feeling of anticipation” (Hume).
The conclusion follows that together all these combined principles,
models, and theories are unable to provide any meaningful account for (1) a
substantial self/ego; (2) the activity of reflexive self-consciousness as
actively circular, reflexive, unified; and/or (3) the active intentionality of
consciousness as purposive.
The only possible locus of a permanent “self identity” in
materialism is the vacuous, sterile concept of an individual’s DNA molecular
composition.
Further, actual self-consciousness, in the guise of
“introspection,” is not possible; the latter is simply and only a perception of
sensations striking the brain; sensations per se, in and of themselves, qua
sensations do not constitute (a) meanings or (b) a self. In this context, the
doctrine of phenomenalism, namely that all we can “know,” i.e. be conscious of,
or cognize, are sense-data, sense qualia, or appearances, leads to the
unacceptable doctrine of the “unobserved observer,” the “unscanned scanner”
(Hume 1955; Mijuskovic, 1976, 1984, 2015). But as Auguste Comte argues, the
instrument of observation and the object of observation cannot be one and the
same. The agent and the product must be distinct, separate. It is impossible to
make a hammer with only a hammer. If all you have are sensations, then you must
have some one to observe the sensations who is not a sensation.
In conclusion, the principles of passive perception (empiricism)
versus active self-consciousnes (rationalism) are radically opposed. They are
conflicting, irreconcilable paradigms, diametrically opposed concepts, which, by
definition cannot be synthesized or combined.
By contrast, Dualism holds that both inert matter and active minds
exist (Plato, Descartes). Idealism maintains that all that exists is mental,
mind-dependent, or spiritual (Leibniz, Kant, Hegel). Rationalism postulates
innate activities and structures within self-consciousness; it assumes
spontaneity, the mind creates and grasps meanings and relations from its own
internal resources; some relations are both synthetic and a priori; (see Chart
for a definition of synthetic a priori); and there is both an irretrievable
subconscious and a retrievable unconscious; Intentionality is the principle that
all consciousness is consciousness of or about something other than the “self”;
it is grounded in the thesis that consciousness intends meanings and relations
beyond, transcendent to the self; consciousness is meaning-intending and
purposeful—not mechanical (Brentano, Husserl, Sartre; Mijuskovic, 1978). Therapy
is grounded in insight, the reflexive ability of self-consciousness to inspect
its own feelings, thoughts, motives, and purposes. Further, Intentionality is
actively linear-–as opposed to behaviorism, which is passively linear---and the
mind projects itself beyond and toward the “lived world.” Very different from
science, humanism argues that the proper study of man is man himself rather than
the motions of particles in space.
In the empiricist tradition, there is no real self. The “self” is
just a loose, disunified “bundle of fleeting impressions, which succeed each
other with inconceivable rapidity”; there are only disunified perceptions
(Hume’s criticism of “personal identity” as metaphysical in the Treatise, Hume,
1955). Further, for both Locke and Hume, in deep sleep and swoons the mind
ceases to think and therefore to exist. This would entail that we are a
different person each time we awake. And according to empiricism, of course,
there can be no unconscious thoughts; it would amount to a contradiction in
terms.
Interestingly and importantly enough, the single premise that the
mind is both immaterial and active results in producing eight distinct
conclusions in the history of ideas and philosophy: (1) the immortality of the
rational soul; (2) the unity of self-consciousness; (3) continuous personal
identity; (4) epistemological idealism; (5) the freedom of self-consciousness;
(6) immanent time-consciousness (as opposed to the measure of motions of bodies
through space); (7) the intrinsic nature of meanings and relations; and (8) the
primacy of qualitative attributes prevailing over quantitative measurements
(Mijuskovic, 1974, 1984, 2015).
This brings us to the theory of unconscious memories (Plotinus,
Cudworth, and Leibniz) as distinct from subconscious, creative, generative
processes. Originally in Plato, the immortality of the soul is connected to its
immaterial essence or nature. It is considered to be simple, spatially
unextended, and therefore indestructible, since it has no parts. Accordingly, as
indicated above, it possesses the intrinsic properties of unity and continuity
because it is always thinking: “The soul always thinks” (Plotinus, Enneads, IV.
3. 30. 1-17). Thus, in the rationalist tradition, we discover the unconscious
seductively enough as grounded in the immortality, unity, continuity, and
identity of the soul as early as Plotinus, Cudworth, and Leibniz (Mijuskovic,
2008-09). Freud’s version of the unconscious is therefore very similar to the
one just outlined and it consists of repressed memories.
But German idealism posits a much deeper, subterranean
subconscious sphere of irrational, spontaneous, creative volitions in the form
of a “will” that is causeless; volitions that are purely unpredictable as they
erupt from seemingly nowhere, from the hidden self. These active forces of
consciousness go much deeper than the Freudian unconscious as they emanate from
a subconscious realm, a sphere of primitive urges, wills, desires, and
destructive impulses. This deepest level thus discloses a mysterious portal
leading into the darker, sinister aspects of the subconscious mind. Philosophers
like Kant, Fichte, Hegel, Schopenhauer, and Nietzsche would mutually agree that
below Freud’s unconscious, which is retrievable in principle, e. g., the
multiple cities of Rome all existing simultaneously (Freud, 1961, page 17),
there are unreachable activities that are intrinsically irretrievable,
inaccessible. Freud’s unconscious is grounded in forgotten painful memories and
his therapeutic measures are predicated on the ability to bring those traumatic
experiences into explicit consciousness so they can be rationally dealt with.
But the hidden, occult, shadowy, intangible instinctual desires and forces of an
irrational will defy any and all translations into recognizable human “motives”
(Mijuskovic, 2015, Chapter Seven, “The Unconscious and the Subconscious”).
In Kant, the creative “productive imagination”—as distinct from the
empirical, associative re-productive imagination---spontaneously generates the
cognitive unity of self-consciousness but it can only be assumed
“hypothetically” (Critique of Pure Reason, A xvii, A 15=B 29). In other words,
there are underlying, generative forces within consciousness itself that are
necessary to bind, hold, and synthesize consciousness into a unity but these
activities remain inaccessible to the conscious mind. Otherwise our sensations
would roll away like tossed marbles on a floor. For how else is it that I know
my sensations and thoughts are mine and not yours unless some previous act of
which I am not aware has already taken place? How is this unity of consciousness
achieved?
But Fichte, although following Kant, breaks new ground by stressing
an affective, instinctual role—as opposed to Kant’s cognitive
interests---arguing for a subconscious irrational, ungrounded will. In effect,
this will, as conceived in idealism, is analogous to God’s creation of the world
and each soul ex nihilo, “out of nothing.”
It is this [subconscious] neglected synthetic activity of the mind which
constructs a unity from separate contrasts and thus preserves a unity linking
both ego and non-ego; it is this alone which makes possible consciousness and
above all as a continuous temporal sequence [i.e. for both the unity of
self-consciousness and immanent time-consciousness in the two Deductions]
(Whyte, 1978).
Again:
Fichte opens up a sequence of philosophers: Schelling, Hegel, Schopenhauer,
and Nietzsche, who developed the conception of the [subconscious] mind as a
dynamic principle underlying conscious reason. For Fichte the light of
consciousness emerges out of the dark of the [subconscious; so Plotinus]. The
unconscious processes of the mind had previously been considered by philosophers
to be mainly concerned with memory and perception; now they became unmistakably
the seat of instinct and will…The apperceptive [self-conscious] faculty of the
mind is an activity which contains the ultimate basis of consciousness but never
itself comes to consciousness” (ibid.).
Just as Freud’s unconscious Id grounds the continuity of the ego,
of personal identity, just so these dark forces of the subconscious constitute
the ultimate nucleus of selfhood, of the narcissistic self, as it grounds an
identity which is impermeable to rational penetration. Therefore, , within the
German idealist tradition, there are (a) subterranean powers that are
subconsciously generative not only in regard to cognitive consciousness, as in
Kant’s concept of the Categories of the Understanding, but also (b) there are
activities producing dark and dangerous emotions, whose ultimate sources are
inaccessible, deeply hidden, and unknowable in principle. These affective,
emotional, uncontrollable, irrational instincts, urges, and destructive forces
can only be indirectly suggested in literature, as in Conrad’s Heart of
Darkness, Gide’s The Immoralist, Golding’s Pincher Martin and Lord of the Flies,
Hesse’s Steppenwolf, Kosinski’s The Painted Bird, and Jung’s Shadow Self
(Mijuskovic, 1979). Their original literary expressions first appear in
Egyptian, Greek, and Roman mythology, in the plays of Sophocles and Aeschylus,
and in medieval man’s obsessional conviction that he is a fatefully sinful
creature. There are more than sufficient reasons why Judaic, Christian, and
Moslem man has struggled against the fear of his own instincts and drives. These
secretive and insidious feelings and thoughts persevere in all of us and only
much too frequently emerge and erupt during our dreams and nightmares, in dark
and violent fantasies, in sports, movies, and more recently video games. We only
sense them as vital forces when we try to descend into the labyrinthine depths
and caverns of loneliness as we unveil the true nucleus of human existence
(Mills, 2002, 2014). The consequences of these considerations are momentous in
terms of potential danger and harm to the self as well as to others. Raging
fantasies of destruction, cruelty, torture, atrocities, and genocide are
engendered as a direct result of narcissistic loneliness both in the individual
and in societies. Freud’s thanatological principles of aggression and death lurk
inside all of us. There is something inhuman, some lurking desire at the bottom
of the human soul that darkly resonates within each of us during intense bouts
of loneliness, feelings of separation, rejection, betrayal, and abandonment.
The first article devoted to loneliness as a subject matter in its
own right is written by a psychoanalyst, Gregory Zilboorg. He describes how the
infant’s narcissistic ego, initially pampered, loved, and admired experiences
feelings of omnipotence, delusions of grandeur, entitlement issues, and
“megalomania.” But as the self develops and its impetuous desires are thwarted
by both mother and society, the ego becomes angry and anxious; it experiences a
sense of separation and intense feelings of loneliness. As the child grows into
adolescence, and adulthood, if this state of tension becomes unduly prolonged
and/or intensified, it can lead to suicide, murder, or both as the synthetic a
priori triad of narcissism, loneliness, and hostility forcefully increases and
manifests itself (Zilboorg, 1938). It can be a lethal dynamic.
Loneliness is intrinsically related to man’s narcissism and narcissism
carries with it more than a seed of malice, of hostility (page 49). Our
instincts today are as primitive as they were a hundred thousands of years ago.
We are no longer cannibals but somewhere deep in our personality lie
cannibalistic drives. And we know things emotionally long before we know them
intellectually.
And it all begins in the cradle:
Here is the nucleus of hostility, hatred, impotent aggression of the lonely
and abandoned. It is the beginning of that intolerant anger which some day
civilization will have to subdue or mental illness discharge into the open. And
if we continue from the crib to the nursery and kindergarten, we can observe,
scene by scene, the enactment of the story entitled narcissism, loneliness, and
megalomania (page 53; Mijuskovic, 1979-80; 1983).
Most instructive is the case of Elliot Rodger, who tried to
penetrate a sorority house in order to murder all its residents because he felt
rejected by young women in general for not sufficiently appreciating him. His
140-page autobiography is replete with narcissistic fantasies of revenge,
hatred, and envy. He experienced powerful feelings of narcissism, which fueled
his entitlement issues and delusions of grandeur; he simply could not understand
why young women were not enamored of him; he endlessly played video games as
substitutes in order to discharge his feelings of jealousy, resentment, and
violence when he observed happy couples; he wanted to kill his younger brother
because he feared his sibling might achieve a happy life while he felt denied:
“If I can’t enjoy this world, I’m not going to let others enjoy it either”; he
expected to win the lottery so he could dominate women with his wealth. Failing
to breach the sorority residence, he managed to kill six students before
committing suicide. For a compelling study in loneliness and hostility see “My
Twisted World by Elliot Rodger” (google, PDF; 5/13/2014, 140 pp.).
But even nations can experience the same lonely sense of real or
imaginary degradation, humiliation, and vilification at the hands of the world
community as the Nazis did in 1933. Already in 1938, Zilboorg anticipates the
atrocities and genocides, the concentration camps of Buchenwald, Aufschwitz, and
Treblinka; Nazism and Fascism following the aftermath of the First World War.
Similarly, Hannah Arendt, a decade later in 1948, echoes the same conviction in
The Origins of Totalitarianism (Arendt, 1976). Today, we can only view with
horror the advent of ISIS with its genocidal atrocities, tortures, suicide
bombers, beheadings, and wanton destruction. What is true of individuals is just
as true of groups/gangs, and nations.
The second article dedicated to the sole theme of loneliness is by
another psychoanalyst, Frieda Fromm-Reichmann. Indeed, she connects loneliness
with the universal sense of failed communication and she equates loneliness with
anxiety (Fromm-Reichmann, 1959).
I have made an attempt in this paper to invite the interest of
psychiatrists to the investigation of the psychodynamics of loneliness as a
significant universal emotional experience with far-reaching psychological
ramifications. I have postulated a significant inter-relatedness between
loneliness and anxiety and suggested the need for further conceptual and
clinical examination in its own right and in its relation to anxiety (italic
mine).
But one cannot experience anxiety without feeling angry as well.
Anxiety and hostility are the dual Janus-faces of loneliness. When we are
frightened by or of others, we are also angry with them. Erich Fromm echoes her
sentiments and in including anxiety to his list he also adds guilt and shame
(Fromm, 1970). The addition of shame is important because generally people will
not admit they are lonely for fear it makes them seem pathetic, pitiful, and
emotional lepers.
Consequently loneliness constitutes an “umbrella concept”; it can
be conceived as subsuming under its extended spokes a cluster of both negative
emotions as well as rich meanings emanating from the nucleus of egoistic
narcissism; it includes a myriad of feelings--“megalomania,” anger, rage,
anxiety, depression, failed communication, shame, guilt, envy, abandonment,
betrayal, revenge, low self-esteem, etc. This is why loneliness is not in the
DSM. It is an umbrella concept; it is not a specific diagnosis. It is rather a
coherent system of synthetic a priori feelings and meanings.
In any case, loneliness is not a disease, not a “disorder.” It is
the “existential” human condition although obviously it has its extreme
pathological expressions (Mijuskovic, 1977b; Yalom, 1980).
Whereas Kant argues that there are transcendental, i.e., “formal”
cognitive synthetic a priori relations/structures in consciousness, e. g.
substance<>accident, cause<>effect, constituting human experience,
in Husserl, however, these syntheses are “material,” i.e. both sensuously
content-full and a priori, e. g., “All colors (quality) are extended
(quantity)”; “All material objects are given perspectivally.” Although they are
distinct concepts, they are always found together; they tell us something about
the world and human nature independently and “logically” prior to experience. By
exploiting Husserl’s method of “free imaginative variation,” we are able to
uncover additional essences/meanings within loneliness and test the ones we are
examining, e. g., abandonment, betrayal, rejection, resentment, etc. (Husserl,
1966). And just as we are able to connect, relate, synthesize, bind essential
meanings together within consciousness, just so we can enlist Husserl’s method
of “free imaginative variation” in order to discover unconscious, hidden
essences—although Husserl would reject in principle any turn to a subconscious
or unconscious element in consciousness. The importance of this imaginative
tool/method is that when someone tells you they are depressed, whether they
realize it or not, loneliness is the underlying dynamic. Or when one admits
having low self-esteem, it is in actuality loneliness which underlies it. And
unless one confronts the underlying reality of loneliness and its negative
implications, one will forever be prevented from overcoming it.
What can be done? What are the possible remedies? Therapeutically
the activity of reflexive self-consciousness promotes and supports rational
insight, i.e. self-analysis, what Freud describes in general terms as the
psychoanalytic method. Self-consciousness is active, reflexive. It is circular.
Thought has the peculiarly self-conscious power, energy, or dynamic to think
about its self and its motives (rationalism). It knows that it knows and what it
knows. And it also has the capacity of realizing that within its deeper self
there exist much darker feelings and thoughts that are irrational. How else to
account for man’s inhumanity to man; the atrocities and genocides that have
continually plagued our past as well as our present and promise to doom us in
the future?
The vital aspect of self-consciousness is rational insight; its
critical cognitive force lies in its function of synthesizing, unifying,
relating, connecting, binding, and structuring the contents and activities of
self-awareness. In Kant, it is these formal, synthetic a priori categories or
relations unifying self and object, cause and effect, etc. that make human
experience possible (the two Deductions, A and B, in the Critique of Pure
Reason). The “external world” conforms to the innate, active structures of the
mind (Kant’s Copernican Revolution, B xvi; Mijuskovic, 2010).
In Freud, these syntheses are simply superficially and cavalierly
attributed to a mythological force: Eros, which discourages further theoretical
exploration or even comment.
[T]he main purpose of Eros—that of uniting and binding---in so far as it
helps toward establishing the unity, or tendency to unity… is particularly
characteristic of the ego (Freud, 1960, page 35).
But although self-consciousness provides us with insight, it can
also entrap, doom, and enervate us in a self-contained, circular brooding
depression. Most often loneliness is mistaken for depression. But as we have
seen, depression or melancholy is only one element. As Freud correctly
speculates, depression can also be viewed as internalized hostility but he
failed to plumb deeper into its universal source---loneliness.
The intentionality, the transcendence, the freedom, the
spontaneity of consciousness also allows us to escape from the confines of
selfhood. As we have seen, phenomenology defines consciousness in terms of the
activity of intentionality, the principle that all consciousness is about or of
something other than its “self”; its active, radiating, directional arrows
target the meaning of an object; a relation; a law; a value, and even the “self”
as beyond its “self” (see Diagram of Theories of Consciousness). Analogous to
its reflexive counterpart, it is active but in a linear fashion as opposed to a
circular one. But unlike its behavioral contrast, although both are
linearly-directed, intentionality spontaneously radiates, transcends, and
explodes from the interiority of consciousness beyond and transcendent to its
reflexive self (Mijuskovic, 1976; 1977, 2015a). As a principle and paradigm of
consciousness, it is endorsed by Brentano, Husserl, and Sartre (Mijuskovic,
1978b). But because both reflexive/self-consciousness and the intentionality of
consciousness are “spontaneous,” active they can be conceived as assuming
mutually supportive roles through their synthetic a priori connections thus
providing both (a) an insight into loneliness as well as (b) the power to escape
its imprisoning confines. Self-consciousness, although offering the possibility
of self-analysis and insight, also presents the danger of restricting the self
solipsistically within a self-enclosed, insular sphere of loneliness. It is
intentionality that provides us with the key for our escape from enervating
loneliness, boredom, and the depression that depletes our energy. To use an
analogy: self-consciousness is like throwing a boomerang that returns to the
agent; intentionality is like an archer targeting a bulls-eye; it is the
difference in thinking about the past and deciding what to do in the
future.
In terms of clinical pathology, we can readily observe the
dysfunctions expressed in bipolar disorders as patients cycle through
alternating episodes of self-conscious depression and intentional mania in their
desperate efforts to escape loneliness..
Both theoria (insight) and praxis (action) are necessary to overcome
loneliness. Nevertheless, it is the practice of intimacy and empathy that is our
salvation. If loneliness is grounded in the threat of constant separations, then
intimacy presents the intentional power of the self to transcend itself; for the
self to connect beyond its self in purposeful activity. The goal is to reduce
and eliminate separations whenever possible. The route from lonely insularity to
intimate attachments travels along the path of affective empathy. Empathy is a
term first coined by Theodor Lipps. He intended it as an aesthetic concept; an
emotional infusion and projection of the self’s feelings of freedom, exuberance,
beauty, and expression into the artistic object: a dancer, a statue, a painting,
a song, a poem, a novel, a movie, etc. Husserl, in the fifth Cartesian
Meditations, following Lipps, interprets it as a cognitive concept, as an
intentional meaning signifying a relation of “ap-presentation” with the other
self; an “an-alogical” placing of my body and consciousness in the place of the
other; a dual “embodiment” (Husserl, 1960). But if so, then Husserl’s concept of
empathy is flawed because it violates his own fundamental principle that
essences always must be universally, necessarily, and immediately, directly
given to consciousness; they cannot be re-presentational; they are essentially
unlike contingent or empirical concepts, which are always mediate, indirect, and
re-presentational (“The veil of perception”). Thus both Lipps and Husserl
mistakenly present empathy as an asymmetrical relation. In other words, the
aesthetic object, the statue for example, does not mutually “ascribe” identical
feelings and meanings of beauty and expression to me. Further, in Husserl’s The
Crisis of the European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology, there is no
guarantee that the other self is simultaneously placing him/herself “in my place
in space,” in a shared “lived world” (Mijuskovic, 2015a, Chapter 4, “Loneliness
and Phenomenology”). Instead I propose that we consider empathy primarily as
affective, as a feeling, an emotion. If we do so, we shall then discover that
unlike sympathy and pity, empathy is transcendentally grounded in mutual
experiences, simultaneous, symmetrical feelings and meanings that intrinsically
relate my self/ego to and with the other ego/self; in sharing the same emotion.
If it did not, then the mutually intended purpose of the two selves in both
providing and receiving support could not be fulfilled. When we do that, we
realize empathy is both a common and an intense experience, much like Maslow’s
conception of “peak experiences” shared a deux. It occurs when two parents share
their grief over the death of their child; when a loving couple learns that one
of them has terminal cancer; when a mother rejoices with her daughter the birth
of her first grandchild; or when two soldiers under attack share their mortal
terror. Whenever two (or more) participants in an event or situation mutually
intensely feel, mean, and experience the same “consciousness,” identical
feelings and meanings, then the synthetic a priori relation of affective,
empathic attachment has occurred and one is not alone or (as) lonely. In those
special moments in time, no one can possibly doubt that s/he is alone in the
world. And so, whatever empathy is it presupposes an activity when both selves
are mutually engaged in identical feelings and meanings. In To Kill a
Mockingbird, Atticus Finch tells his young daughter, Scout:
First of all, if you can learn a simple trick, Scout, you’ll get along
better with all kinds of folk. You never really understand a person until you
consider things from his point of view—until you climb into his skin and walk
around in it (Lee, 1960).
This is not only a sound ethical principle but a therapeutic one as
well.
We may thus conclude that genuine friendship and therapy are both
founded in a dialogue that enhances empathic intimacy and the quality of
affective attachments thereby avoiding the sense of separation and its
concomitant fear of loneliness (Lynch, 1975, 2000). In such situations,
loneliness will be (to a certain extent and for a while) transcended. Together
loneliness and intimacy once more describe the twin features of man’s
existential being; both his punishment and his salvation. And, in this
recognition, each of us should acknowledge that the painful travail of Sisyphus
also exhibits his eternal self-conscious dignity. Thus intimacy consists in a
mutual sharing between two selves of feelings, a constant communication of
meanings between them, and an unbreakable continuity of mutual values.
Further, intimacy is also grounded and requires physical proximity;
one cannot be intimate at a distance; it is constituted by mutual trust; mutual
affection; and mutual age-appropriate respect.
By contrast materialism, empiricism, and behaviorism offer a hollow
understanding of loneliness. Ultimately it is the difference between a rich
humanism and a materialism and cognitive behaviorism which offers only a sterile
pseudo-science that ends by turning humans into machines and computers.
In the preceding, I have tried to show that the fear of loneliness
is primary and universal; why this is so; its consequences; and what can be done
about it.
And God stepped out on space,
And He looked around and said,
“I’m lonely—
I’ll make me a world.”
Then God walked around,
And God looked around,
On all that He had made,
He looked at his sun,
And He looked at his moon,
And He looked at his little stars,
He looked at his world,
With all its living things,
And God said, “I’m lonely still.”
And God thought and thought,
Till He thought, “I’ll make me a man.”
This great God,
Like a mammy bending over her baby,
Kneeled down in the dust,
Toiling over a lump of clay,
Till he shaped it in His own image:
Then into it He blew the breath of life.
And man became a living soul.
The Creation, A Negro Spiritual, J. W. Johnston
For information about Ben Mijuskovic's book, see this link: http://mbsmagazin.blogspot.co.uk/2013/04/ben-mijuskovic-loneliness.html
For information about Ben Mijuskovic's book, see this link: http://mbsmagazin.blogspot.co.uk/2013/04/ben-mijuskovic-loneliness.html
REFERENCES
*Talk presented at Brunel University, October 30, 2015
Arendt, H. (1976). The Origins of Totalitarianism. San Diego: Harcourt,
Brace & Jovanovic, 475.
Augustine, St. (1960). The Confessions of St. Augustine. New York:
Doubleday, Chapter 5, 45.
Berthold-Bond, D. (1995). Hegel’s Theory of Madness. Albany: State
University of New York Press, 40-42.
Cornford, F. M. (1964). Plato’s Theory of Knowledge. London and New York:
Routledge & Kegan Paul, 228-234.
Freud, S. (1960). The Ego and the Id. New York: W. W. Norton, 48.
Freud, S. (1961a). Civilization and Its Discontents. New York: W. W.
Norton, 13-15.
Freud, S. Beyond the Pleasure Principle. (1961b). New York: W. W. Norton,
32-33.
Ibid., 51-52.
Fromm, E. (1970). The Art of Loving. New York: Harper & Row, 6-7
Fromm-Reichmann, F. (1959). Loneliness, Psychiatry: Journal for the Study
of Interpersonal Processes, 22:1, 1-15.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1971). Hegel’s Philosophy of Mind. Oxford: Clarendon
Press. Section 408, Note.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1977). Phenomenology of Spirit. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, Sense-Certainty, 58-66.
Ibid., Self-Consciousness: Lordship and Bondage, 111-119.
Hume, D. (1955). A Treatise of Human Nature. Of personal identity,
251-253.
Husserl, E. (1960). Cartesian Meditations. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff,
Fifth Meditation.
Husserl. E. (1962). Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology. New
York: Collier, Section 84.
Husserl, E. (1966). Meaning and Judgment. Evanston: Northwestern University
Press, 383.
Husserl, E. (1970). Crisis of the European Sciences and Transcendental
Phenomenology. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
James, W. (1950). The Principles of Psychology. New York: Dover, I,
488.
Kant, I. (1958). Critique of Pure Reason. London: Macmillan & Co., A
107-110; B 131,B 274-279.
Kant, I. (2011). Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, “Carazan’s Dream,” 16-17.
Kierkegaard, S. (1974). Fear and Trembling and the Sicknes onto Death.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press,30-37.
Kojeve, A. (1969). Introduction to the Reading of Hegel. New York: Basic
Books.
Lee, H. (1960). To Kill a Mockingbird. New York: Grand Central Press,
39.
Lynch, J. (1975). The Broken Heart: The Medical Consequences of Loneliness.
New York: Basic Books.
Lynch, J. (2000). A Cry Unheard. Baltimore: Bancroft Press.
Mahler, M. Pine, F., & Bergman, A. (1975). (Eds.). The Psychological
Birth of the Human Infant. New York: Basic Books, 111.
Ibid., 78-79 and passim.
Mijuskovic, B. (1974). The Achilles of Rationalist Arguments: The
Simplicity, Unity, and Identity of Thought and Soul from the Cambridge
Platonists to Kant. A Study in the History of Ideas. The Hague: Martinus
Nijhoff.
Mijuskovic, B. (1976). The simplicity argument versus a materialist theory
of consciousness, Philosophy Today.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.